SNERX.COM/MATH Last Updated 2025/8/1 • Read Time 22min • Discord
______________________________________________________________________________________
I never learned math in school, so as an adult I have been trying to teach it to
myself. The things I have found on this page are probably wrong, and the things I am
not wrong about were likely discovered long ago. This is just for fun.
Separate Cardinalities of Zero: Infinity and zero share a lot of properties in common.
You can multiply or divide infinity by any number and it is still infinity. You can
multiply or divide zero by any number and it is still zero. Neither infinity nor zero
are numbers since they both signify the lack of quantity. Both represent limits of
calculation since infinity is an upper bounds to quantity and zero is a lower bounds
to quantity. Further, dividing any number by zero returns infinity and dividing any
number by infinity returns zero.
Given the similarities, and since there are different kinds of infinites, I wondered
if there is also a difference in kind of zeros. You would think we couldn't use the
same diagonalization method for zeros that Cantor uses for infinites since infinite
lists can be enumerated by all the real numbers and zero is just one entity, but by
using infinitesimals like 0.001 or 0.0099, we have an infinitely enumerable set of
zeros we can index and apply diagonalization to just the same as Cantor did.
The objection to this would be that infinitesimals are not distinct values and do not
qualify as being distinct in identity, but without talking to mathematicians, I have
no idea if this is true.
Infinite Series & Randomness: If you have an infinite series of whole numbers from one
to positive infinity, and you randomly select a number from that series, then the
number of digits of that selected number will also be infinite. That is, the average
length of the series 1-9 is 1, since each number in the series is 1 digit long, but the
average length of the series 1-99 is closer to 2, and the average length of the series
1-999 is closer to 3, and so on, trending towards infinity. So the average number of
digits for numbers in a series of integers from one to infinity is infinite. Average
means that roughly half the numbers in the series are longer than the other half, and
roughly half are shorter. But half of infinity is still infinity, thus all the numbers
available to pick must be infinite in length. But no natural number can be infinite in
length, so what gives?
Conversely, there is no real randomness in infinity. If you are to randomly pick a
number from one to ten, each number has a one-out-of-ten chance of being picked, but
if you are to randomly pick a number from one to infinity, each number has infinitely
low odds of being picked. I posit that since these odds asymptotically approach zero,
the odds of randomly picking any number out of an infinite series is truly zero,
meaning you simply could not pick a number. As further explanation, James Torre
pointed me to the impossibility of a measure for the Naturals for why this random
selection fails.
Problems for Cantor's Diagonalization: This is a weird way to argue for ℤ and ℝ not
having separate cardinalities. There are three issues I have with diagonalization.
The first occurs when swaping the lists; if you put the natural numbers in a list
denominated by the real numbers instead of the other way around (the way Cantor does
it). If this were valid, the conclusion would be that the set of natural numbers is
larger (and uncountable) than the set of real numbers (which are then the countable
set), a contradiction since this set contains the natural set. To demonstrate this,
look at the following images modified from a Veritasium video.
Above, you see all I have done is swapped the natural index numbers on the left with
the list of real numbers on the right from 0.0 to 1.0. The randomized list of natural
numbers is enumerated just the same in the right list as the real numbers are in the
left list. All we do now is apply the diagonalization technique Cantor uses on the new
list the same as the old list, shown below.
What you see here is that the new natural number we generate from the diagonalization
method similarly 'does not appear in the list', much the same as the new real number
Cantor generates from the diagonalization method. My version with the swapped lists is
directly addressed here and the above issue is considered a non-problem because natural
numbers cannot be infinite in length. However, it's not impossible to have infinitely
long numbers since we do have some numbers that are infinite in length, like the p-adic
numbers. So maybe this is still worth considering.
For the second issue I have, I believe his derivation of different cardinalities is
due to his mixing of potential infinity with actual infinity, something already known
to be improper in physics as far back as their discovery by Aristotle. Whether you use
Cantor's original list or my reversed list, both ways require the use of potential
infinity for the index numbers and actual infinity for the numbers enumerated to the
right of the index. So of course this would appear to be different kinds of infinity,
because you have begged the question and baked a pre-supposed conclusion into the
formulation of its proof.
My third issue with Cantor's diagonalization is that it requires the ordering of his
real numbers to be random, as reordering the list from smallest to largest real number
demonstrates the diagonalized new number in fact already appears on the list. If
Cantor's list was in order from smaller to larger infinite decimals, we would see the
list ordered as 0.111, then 0.112, 0.113, and so on. If we then applied diagonalization
we would get 0.2 from the first real, 0.02 from the second, 0.002 from the third, and
so on, resulting in 0.22 as our newly generated real number. But of course, when
ordered from smallest to largest decimal, 0.22 would appear later in the list.
I contend that if you don't believe I applied Cantor's diagonalization properly, then
you have not been careful to note the kind of infinities I used. In my prior example,
I do not mix potential with actual infinity, and thereby the list of 0.11n's we
enumerated earlier results in an infinite number of reals that lead with 0.11, meaning
we generate an infinite series of 2's. If you think this problem is resolved by baking
the idea of uncountability back into real numbers, then simply swap the naturals with
the reals as I did in the pictures earlier and you'll see the problem I just described
reoccurs.
So even if one or two of these issues can be resolved, the third will re-assert
itself, making the notion of distinct cardinality between sets of infinites in math an
untennable position. I know I am horribly wrong about this and I appreciate someone who
knows better taking the time to explain to me how this actually works.
Decimals With Multiple Infinite Sections: 1/3 = 0.33, and 2/3 = 0.66, but what numbers
out of a whole give us the other repeating decimals? If we wanted 0.66 out of 1 whole
instead of 2, we get the following:
╭─────────────
│ 1 ÷ x = 0.66
│ 1 = 0.66 • x
│ x = 1 ÷ 0.66
│ x = 1.5
╰─────────────
As a controversial statement, I contend that this number is actually 1.50015. Why and
how? Dividing 1 by 0.666, we get 1.5015, by 0.6666 we get 1.50015, by 0.6666666666 we
get 1.50000000015, and so on. By 0.66 what we get is an infinite series of infinites,
namely the infinite bar between 15's, that is 1.50015001500, repeating. This is the
same as saying 1.5 with an infinite series of zeros following it, and then after
infinite zeros there is a 15 followed by another infinite series of zeros, and so on.
Another way of saying this is that as the divisor grows in decimal length, so too do
the number of zeros between the numbers of the decimal of the quotient. Therefore
with an infinitely repeating decimal divisor you get infinitely repeating zeros
followed by a finite series of numbers, the set of which itself then infinitely
repeats, in the quotient.
I've had people argue with me that, "This is not how fractions work," and if we were
using whole-number fractions, they would be right, but I'm not concerned with
whole-number fractions; the property I describe deals with numbers in decimal format.
The closest thing to this I have been able to find online are Shanks' numbers, but
those are distinct in scope and application. I have written out some of the other
numbers below so you can see their weird properties:
╭─────────────────────────
│ 1 ÷ x = 0.11
│ 1 = 0.11 • x
│ x = 1 ÷ 0.11
│ x = 9.00900900 repeating
╰─────────────────────────
This means 9.009 is the bar number attained from 0.11. To re-iterate why this happens
we can follow the finite series, which results in:
╭───────────────────────────
│ 1 ÷ 0.1 = 10
│ 1 ÷ 0.11 = 9.0909
│ 1 ÷ 0.111 = 9.009009
│ 1 ÷ 0.1111 = 9.00090009
│ 1 ÷ 0.11111 = 9.0000900009
╰───────────────────────────
You keep adding zeros per n decimals of 0.11 from here, ultimately giving us 9.009.
A list of these follows.
For 1 ÷ 0.11 we get 9.009
For 1 ÷ 0.22 we get 4.50045
For 1 ÷ 0.33 we get 3.003
For 1 ÷ 0.44 we get 2.2500225
For 1 ÷ 0.55 we get 1.80018
For 1 ÷ 0.66 we get 1.50015
For 1 ÷ 0.77 we get 1.2857142857142857142870012857 (see below)
For 1 ÷ 0.88 we get 1.125001125
For 1 ÷ 0.99 we get 1.001
Notice the strangness of 0.77's bar number and how no other number has the same level
of noise so far. The way it resolves is somewhat dynamic too:
╭───────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────
│ 1 ÷ 0.7 = 1.42857142857
│ 1 ÷ 0.77 = 1.29870129870
│ 1 ÷ 0.777 = 1.28700128700
│ 1 ÷ 0.7777 = 1.28584287000128584287000
│ 1 ÷ 0.77777 = 1.28572714298571557144142870000128572714298571557144142870000
│ 1 ÷ 0.777777 = 1.28571557142985714414285842857271428700000128571557142985714414285842857271428700000
│ 1 ÷ 0.7777777 = 1.28571441428572714285842857155714287000000128571441428572714285842857155714287000000
│ 1 ÷ 0.77777777 = 1.28571429857142870000000128571429857142870000000
│ 1 ÷ 0.777777777 = 1.28571428700000000128571428700000000
│ 1 ÷ 0.7777777777 = 1.28571428584285714287000000000128571428584285714287000000000
│ 1 ÷ 0.77777777777 = 1.28571428572714285714298571428571557142857144142857142870000000000
│ 1 ÷ 0.777777777777 = 1.28571428571557142857142985714285714414285714285842857142857271428571428700000000000
╰───────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────
This is strange since it resolves to an infinite period in the bar number and further
there are two infinite sequences within the general infinite sequence (demarcated by
the double-bars). I do not know why the bar number for 0.77 does not have a finite
period length, even though all the others do.
1 ÷ 1.22 is neat, resolving as:
╭─────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────
│ 1 ÷ 1.2 = 0.833
│ 1 ÷ 1.22 = 0.819672131147540983606557377049180327868852459016393442622950
│ 1 ÷ 1.222 = 0.818330605564648117839607201309328968903436988543371522094926350245499181669394435351882160392...
│ 1 ÷ 1.2222 = 0.818196694485354279168712158402880052364588447062673866797578137784323351333660612011127475045000
│ 1 ÷ 1.22222 = 0.81... (the period length is 29,216 digits long)
╰─────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────────
This one is weird to me because 1 ÷ 1.22 is just 0.81, but the finite sequence
leading up to it is really dynamic.
Most of this will probably never be looked at by anyone or or be useful for anything,
but since there are different kinds of infinities in math, the countable infinity in
the number 0.001 can be overcome when divided by a number that is an uncountable
infinity. The infinite part of 0.001 can be skipped over by an uncountable infinity,
leaving the 1 at the end as a non-arbitrary part of the divisor. Maybe what I've been
calling the 'bar' numbers above have a possible application in cleaning up infinites.
As a big stretch, fractional divisors in equations for physical systems that result
in very fuzzy statistical outcomes could probably be cleaner by exploiting this
property since infinite values appear often in those systems.
Goldbach's Conjecture: If not already familiar with the conjecture, read this. All
even numbers are predicated off of 2, and 2 is a prime, so all reduction of numbers
predicated by 2 can be reduced to primes of the predication value, which in this case
is 2 (so 2 primes). The generalization then is such that any member of a factor-tree
based on some number X will inherit properties of X and will be reducible to an
X-unit-count that share at least one of those given properties.
The way this looks for the existing conjecture: Every number factorable by 2, past 2,
can be expressed by 2 units of some property of 2 (namely primehood).
The way this looks for new conjectures:
1 — Every number factorable by 1 (all whole numbers), past 1, can be expressed by 1
unit of some property of 1 (namely empty product or unity/identity).
3 — Every number factorable by 3, past 3, can be expressed by 3 units of some property
of 3 (namely merseene primes or fermat primes); effectively the weak conjecture.
π — Every number factorable by π, past π, can be expressed by π units of some property
of π (namely irrational numbers or transcendental numbers).
2 — Every even integer greater than 2 can be expressed as the DIFFERENCE of 2 primes.
The last example is an augmented version of Goldbach's Conjecture showing that unit
relations are arbitrary so long as the relations are of non-arbitrary units
themselves. The point of this is to show that there is a generalized form of the
conjecture that lets us posit any number of equally plausible relations/patterns, and
if Goldbach is right about his conjecture, then so too must all the other conjectures
of the same form be correct.